










Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Prepare for your exams
Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points to download
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Community
Ask the community for help and clear up your study doubts
Discover the best universities in your country according to Docsity users
Free resources
Download our free guides on studying techniques, anxiety management strategies, and thesis advice from Docsity tutors
Hume's arguments against rationalist and powers-based theories of causation and applies them to counterfactual theories. The author argues that Hume's considerations against these theories can be used to demonstrate their inadequacy. The document also discusses Hume's understanding of causation and its relation to counterfactuals.
Typology: Lecture notes
1 / 18
This page cannot be seen from the preview
Don't miss anything!
The Self in Deep Ecology: A Response to Watson Joshua Anderson Draft; co not cite Final Version of Record: Humanities Bulletin 2 .1 (2019): 36- 49 Available at: https://www.journals.lapub.co.uk/index.php/HB/article/view/473/ Abstract : What is offered here is an interpretation of Hume’s views on causation. While it might not be literally Hume’s view, it is certainly consistent with Hume, and is probably what Hume should say on causation, in light of recent developments in science and logic. As a way in, it is argued that the considerations that Hume brings against rationalist theories of causation can be applied to counterfactual theories of causation. Since, counterfactuals, possible worlds and modality were not ideas that would have been overly familiar to Hume, some supplementation of Hume’s arguments will be necessary. Keywords: causation, counterfactuals, David Hume, David Lewis In both A Treatise of Human Nature and An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding David Hume famously argues against the then current rationalist conceptions of causation. Hume believes that since there is no impression of a power causal influence or necessary connection, rationalist understandings of causation cannot be correct. Instead, Hume argues, what one does have is the constant conjunction of cause c and effect e and the expectation that e will follow c. In this article I will argue that the considerations that Hume brings against rationalist and powers theories of causation can be applied to present-day counterfactual theories of causation. That is not to say that Hume is right. Rather, if his arguments are effective against the rationalist and powers theories, then they are effective against counterfactual theories. Now, counterfactuals, possible worlds and modality—despite the influence of Leibniz—were not ideas that would have been overly familiar to Hume. Thus, some reconstruction and supplementation of Hume’s arguments will be necessary.
Actually, this article serves a larger purpose; I aim to offer an understanding of Hume’s theory of causation. By having Hume engage the counterfactual theory of causation, a better understanding of Hume’s ideas regarding causation, generally, can be had. The understanding of causation offered here, certainly, might not have been Hume’s. Instead it what Hume should say about causation in light of recent developments in science and logic. One final point should be made clear; the counterfactual theory, which I will suggest that Hume must reject, is a characterization of the view, but I feel this is a legitimate approach sense the rationalist conception of causation, which Hume actually criticizes, is a characterization of that view. Moreover, the subtleties of the counterfactual theory—such as “centering,” and more detailed understandings of pre-emption—are certainly granted, but the more “metaphysics” that is built into the system, would seem, at least prima facie, to be objectionable to Hume. Thus, it is not necessary to do complete justice to counterfactual theories. This article will progress in the following way. First, there will be a brief overview of the argument that Hume presents in An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding against the rationalist/powers notion of causation. Then, there will be a presentation of a generic version of a counterfactual theory of causation. Next, Hume’s argument will be restructured in order to show that the counterfactual theory of causation is problematic in a way similar to rationalist and powers based theories of causation, relative to Hume’s argument, and potential objections that a counterfactual causation theorist might raise will be addressed. Finally, there will be a discussion of Hume’s understanding of causation and how it does relate to counterfactuals, since Hume does at one point “define” causation counterfactually.
after repeated instances of “similar” causes followed by “similar” effects that one comes to believe that there is a causal relation between the two. All events seem entirely loose and separate. One event follows another; but we never can observe any tie between them. They seem conjoined , but never connected. And as we can have no idea of any thing which never appeared to our outward sense or inward sentiment, the necessary conclusion seems to be that we have no idea of connexion or power at all (Hume 1975, 74). To be consistent with his empiricist theory of meaning, if it is in fact the case that there is not an idea that corresponds to the causal relation, Hume would have to conclude that causal-talk would be meaningless. However, Hume does not draw such a conclusion; rather he tries to figure out what one could mean when using causal-talk. In essence, Hume puts forward his own “theory of causation”. For Hume, causation amounts to the constant conjunction of two events combined with an expectation that one event will follow the other. So, although “[w]e suppose that there is some connexion between them; some power in the one, by which it infallibly produces the other, and operates with the greatest certainty and strongest necessity” it is really just a custom, habit or feeling (Hume 1975, 75). Further, “[t]his connexion, therefore, which we feel in the mind, this customary transition of the imagination from one object to its usual attendant, is the sentiment or impression from which we form the idea of power or necessary connexion” (Hume 1975, 75). In other words, it is the feeling that provides the content for the idea of causation. Thus, to Hume’s mind anyway, causation has been vindicated, deflated as it may be; at least it is not meaningless. The purpose of this section of the article was to introduce Hume’s arguments against rationalist/powers understandings of causation. There are four important points that need to be taken away from the discussion thus far. First, for Hume, rationalist conceptions of causations are not adequate by the mere fact that one cannot come to an idea of a necessary connection between cause and effect by a priori reasoning. Second, since causation is not a “relation of ideas” it must pertain to “matters of fact” and is therefore, radically contingent. By “radically contingent” is meant that for any matter of fact, there is no contradiction in assuming its opposite, or for any matter of fact its denial is always possible. Third, empirically based powers theories of causation are not adequate since there is no impression of any power that would underwrite the causal relation. Finally, Hume presents a
deflationary account of causation where the causal relation is understood as a feeling, or expectation, in the mind of the observer that the occurrence of a particular event (cause) will be followed by particular event (effect), and the expectation comes about because of the constant conjunction of similar causes and effects in the past.
counterfactuals: O( c ) □→ O( e ) and ~O( c ) □→ ~O( e )” (Lewis 1986, 166-167). More formally, Lewis’ point can be represented as: ( e causally depends on c ) ↔ ((O( c ) □→ O( e )) & (~O( c ) □→ ~O( e ))). Notice that if c and e do occur, then the left side of the conjunct is automatically true, so whether or not e causally depends on c depends on the truth of the right side of the conjunct, and similarly regarding the case when c and e do not occur—i.e. the right side of the conjunct is automatically true, et cetera. However, for simplicity, one can disregard the O-predicate and then ( e causally depends on c ) ↔ (( c □→ e ) & (~ c □→ ~ e )), which is basically Lewis’ take on Hume’s “definition”, noted above, with the important difference that Lewis is talking about causal dependence, and not causation, per se. However, Lewis does think that “[c]ausal dependence among actual events implies causation [… but not] the converse [, and this is important because, for Lewis c]ausation must always be transitive; causal dependence may not be; so there can be causation without causal dependence” (Lewis 1986, 167). Bringing everything together, in a general way, a counterfactual theory of causation can be expressed thusly: ( e causally depends on c ) ↔ (( c □→ e ) & (~ c □→ ~ e )) (( c □→ e ) & (~ c □→ ~ e )) is true ↔ ( c □→ e ) is true and (~ c □→ ~ e ) is true c □→ e is true (nonvacuously) ↔ (for any world w ) all the closest worlds (to w ) where c is true e is also true ~ c □→ ~ e is true (nonvacuously) ↔ (for any world w ) all the closest worlds (to w ) where ~ c is true ~ e is also true More simply, and generically, though, the counterfactual theory can be stated formally as ( c is the cause of e ) ↔ ( c □→ e )—irrespective of the possible-world truth conditions.
To begin, Hume argues that rationalist and powers theories of causation cannot be true. First, rationalist conceptions of causation are inadequate by the mere fact that one cannot come to an idea of a necessary connection between cause and effect by a priori reasoning. Second, since causation is not a “relation of ideas” it must pertain to “matters of fact” and, therefore, for any matter of fact its denial is always possible—thus, there can be no necessary connection. Third, empirically based powers theories of causation are inadequate since there is no impression of any power that would provide content for the idea of a causal relation. Now the rough and general version of a counterfactual theory of causation is: c causes e , just in case, c □→ e , but notice that because causation is a matter of fact the denial is always possible. Thus, it is possible that c could obtain, and e would fail to obtain—i.e. if c were to happen, e might not happen, or formally: c ◊→ ~ e. It is clear that Hume entertained such a possibility when he discusses billiard balls in the Enquiry. When I see, for instance, a Billiard-ball moving in a straight line towards another; even suppose motion in the second ball should by accident be suggested to me, as the result of their contact or impulse; may I not conceive, that a hundred different events might as well follow from that cause? May not both these balls remain at absolute rest? May not the first ball return in a straight line, or leap off from the second in any line or direction? All these suppositions are consistent and conceivable. Why then should we give the preference to one, which is no more consistent or conceivable than the rest (Hume 1975, 29-30)? Further, by definition—in fact Lewis’ definition^1 —(Φ □→ Ψ) ↔ ~(Φ ◊→ ~Ψ), or in the cause and effect language that is being used ( c □→ e ) ↔ ~( c ◊→ ~ e ). Yet, Hume believes that c ◊→ ~ e , and, in fact, because c ◊→ ~ e is true, the rationalist conception of causation is false. So, if c ◊→ ~ e is true, then c □→ e cannot be true, by a simple application of biconditional modus tollens. Hence, it cannot be the case that c causes e , just in case, c □→ e , if one wants to maintain causal talk. Formally, the above argument goes as follows:
causal in the way that one normally thinks about causation. Of the four types, three seem particularly problematic and these are: (i) cases of logical/analytic dependence, (ii) when one event is a constituent aspect of another event, and (iii) when one event determines another, but not causally (Kim 1993, 205- 2 06). Kim gives the following examples for each: (i) “If yesterday had not been Monday, today would not be Tuesday.” (ii) “If I had not written ‘r’ twice in succession, I would not have written ‘Larry’.” (iii) “If my sister had not given birth at t , I would not have become an uncle at t ” (Kim 1993, 205-206). The reason that the overly broad application of counterfactual dependence is problematic is that it requires “piling on epicycles” to make the theory work (Lewis 1986, 160). What is meant here is that not only does an adequate counterfactual theory of causation have to explain genuine cases of causation, but it also has to have something above and beyond the causal explanation that can, in a principled way, distinguish genuine cases of causation from mere cases of counterfactual dependence. As to the second problem, it is important to be reminded of what Hume’s “definition” of causation is. Hume states that “we may define cause to be an object followed by another, and where all the objects similar to the first are followed by objects similar to the second. Or in other words where, if the first object had not been, the second never had existed ” (Hume 1975, 76). Lewis believes that Hume is actually putting forward two distinct definitions, one regarding a sort of regularity principle and one, the part following “in other words”, as a counterfactual theory. Lewis does not believe that the latter is a mere restatement, or clarification, of the former; he believes that the latter “propose[s] something altogether different” (Lewis 1986, 160). Yet, it is unclear why that would be the case—i.e. why the latter is something altogether different, and not a mere restatement, or clarification, of the former. The fact of the matter is that Hume says “in other words”. Now it seems fair to assume that Hume would mean what is normally meant by “in other words,” which is that Hume is articulating the same principle in two different ways and not putting forward something altogether different, as Lewis maintains. It seems reasonable to assume that had Hume been putting forward two different principles he would have said as much, for example we may define cause to be an object followed by another, and where all the objects similar to the first are followed by objects similar to the second. Or [another possible way we could define cause is that] where, if the first object had not been, the second never had existed ” (Hume 1975, 76).
However, one does not need to just split hairs with Lewis over Hume’s wording to get the very point under consideration here across—i.e. that Hume is putting forward one definition and a restatement thereof, and not two distinct definitions. Lewis maintains that the regularity theory of causation—a theory based on the first half of Hume’s definition—is problematic for at least three reasons. First, a regularity theory cannot adequately differentiate between genuine causes and cases of confusion between cause and effect, where it is not that c is the cause of e , but where it is actually that e is the cause of c. Second, a regularity theory cannot adequately distinguish cases of genuine cases of causation and epiphenomenon. Finally, a regularity theory cannot adequately handle cases of preemption (Lewis 1986, 160). The problem is that the counterfactual theory of causation struggles with the exact same issues, as Paul Horwich has pointed out: “What Lewis said about regularity analyses is now a fair assessment of the counterfactual approach” (Horwich 1993, 216). Kim draws a similar conclusion when he states that: If we compare the classical regularity theory with Lewis’s account […] it is by no means clear that the latter fairs better than the former” (Kim 1993, 207). Now, it is by no means decisive that just because a counterfactual theory of causation is left wanting, in the same way that a regularity theory of causation is, leads to the conclusion that Hume is not putting forward two distinct understandings of causation. However, coupling the fact that the two theories are left wanting in the same way with the fact that Hume says “in other words” instead of, for example, “or, alternatively”, gives one reason to believe that Hume is not putting forward two distinct understandings. I now turn to some objections that the counterfactual theorist might have regarding the argument I have presented against the counterfactual theory of causation. First, the counterfactual theorist might contend that the argument fails to appreciate the truth conditions for counterfactuals that Lewis puts forward. Second, that the argument does not take seriously the caveats that Lewis puts forth before he even begins his presentation of a counterfactual theory of causation. It is not the case that the above argument fails to appreciate the truth conditions for counterfactuals, but the introduction of possible worlds does complicate things. So, even if the truth conditions are granted, it is hard to see how one could make a principled distinction regarding closest worlds. As Alan Hajek has argued “the connection between similarity and the truth-conditions for counterfactuals is far less straightforward than has been widely assumed” (Hajek 2018, 14). His point is that for any ordering for determining similarity of
The problem is, though, that a Humean understanding of natural laws is, qualitatively, not different from a Humean understanding of causation. Thus, assuming the laws of nature at the outset would appear to be, possibly, question-begging. More importantly, the current best science—quantum mechanics, for example—maintains that the laws of nature as we know them are indeterministic and probabilistic, which again if there is a greater than zero probability that c & ~ e then the might-counterfactual holds. “And it isn’t just the canonical quantum mechanical examples—radioactive decay, spin measurements on a particle in a Stern-Gerlach apparatus, and so on—that are indeterministic. The indeterminism reaches medium-sized dry goods (and even oversized wet ones), just less obviously so” (Hajek 2018, 7). Hajek gives a billiard ball example to drive the point home, which is not that different from Hume’s for establishing that a rationalist conception of causation is untenable. Two billiard balls colliding may approximate a deterministic system, but even they are not immune from quantum mechanical indeterminism. One ball might spontaneously tunnel through the other, to China, or to the North Star— incredibly unlikely, to be sure but possible. Thus I cannot truly say “if the cue ball were to hit the 8 ball, the 8 ball would begin rolling” (Hajek 2018, 7). Finally, Lewis has argued elsewhere that he believes that the counterfactual theory of causation does function in indeterministic settings (Lewis 1986). Thus, the caveat can be ignored, even by Lewis’ own light. However, it should be noted that even determinism would not eliminate the chanciness that is required to make the might-counterfactual true. Hajek points out that a prime example occurs in statistical mechanics—a deterministic system—with Maxwell’s demon, but “[t]he point generalizes to other deterministic systems. For every set of initial conditions in which the cue ball hits the 8 ball and each follows an expected trajectory, there is a nearby initial condition in which the balls behave anomalously” (Hajek 2018, 20). And yet again, these are just the types of reasons that Hume did, or would, give to refute the rationalist conception of causation. To be clear, I am taking Hume in his most skeptical mood here. Thus, holding the laws of nature fixed runs afoul of Hume’s arguments against induction. Second, even granting that the laws of nature hold, because of quantum indeterminism and deterministic chanciness—discussed above—the might-counterfactual still holds, and the argument goes
through. The onus would be on the counterfactual theorist to explain why, and in what sense, the might-counterfactual does not hold, in a non-question-begging way. What Lewis is doing with his similarity-of-worlds truth conditions is to block logically possible outcomes from acting as defeaters for the would-counterfactual. What the claim here is, and in Hume’s spirit, is to suggest that the actual chanciness of natural laws opens up the modal neighborhood which allows the might-counterfactual to be true, even if highly unlikely. Further, appealing to some sort of nomic dependence that holds between cause and effect, and which would make the would-counterfactual true, is prima facie , a response not available to the counterfactual theorist, as understood in this article. Lewis, for example is quite clear that “[i]t is essential to distinguish counterfactual and causal dependence from […] nomic dependence ” (Lewis 1986, 167). Granted, in his less skeptical mood Hume allows for natural necessity, which, for example, plays an important role in his discussion of miracles (Hume 1975, 109-131). But, again, given that “natural necessity,” understood as the laws of nature holding, is probabilistic and chancy the might-counterfactual will almost always be true making the would- counterfactual false. Finally, it is not claimed that counterfactual theories of causation are false, or that Hume is right. The point of this article is to demonstrate that the types of arguments that Hume uses against rationalist and powers conceptions of causation can be applied to counterfactual theories. The counterfactual theorist might have responses, just as a rationalist or powers theorist might have responses, but those are issues that extend beyond the scope of this article.
“ where, if the first object had not been, the second never had existed ,” helps explain what the feeling of expectation is (Hume 1975, 76). Now, it seems that a counterfactual theory of causation would seem to make some sense, for Hume. To be clear, it is not the case that ( c causes e ) ↔ ( c □→ e ), but something more like: “When I say that c causes e , I basically mean that when I observe that c , I expect that e would follow.” Further, the possible worlds semantics can also be explained in a similar way. Instead of saying that in all the nearby possible worlds where c obtains, e also obtains, it would be something more like: “Based on my experience, if the world continues as I expect it to, then whenever c obtains, e also does.” So, there is an additional caveat to the original thesis of this article. If a counterfactual theorist does not have anything stronger in mind than this psychological/linguistic explanation of causation mentioned above, then it does not seem that Hume would find it problematic. If they do, then it would seem that Hume would reject those stronger types of counterfactual theories of causation, and he would do so for reasons quite similar to the reasons he has for rejecting rationalist and powers based theories of causation.
Notes (^1) See for example, Lewis (1973).