






Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Prepare for your exams
Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points to download
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Community
Ask the community for help and clear up your study doubts
Discover the best universities in your country according to Docsity users
Free resources
Download our free guides on studying techniques, anxiety management strategies, and thesis advice from Docsity tutors
This document delves into the philosophical debate between free will and determinism, discussing how natural evil can be explained through the free will defense and the implications of determinism on human agency. Proponents of free will argue that even natural evil can be attributed to free will, either through the actions of nonhuman agents or the consequences of human choices. Determinism, on the other hand, asserts that every event has a cause and that our actions are predetermined by prior conditions and laws of nature. the conflict between free will and determinism and the implications of each view on moral responsibility and the nature of reality.
What you will learn
Typology: Study notes
1 / 12
This page cannot be seen from the preview
Don't miss anything!
Last time we ended our discussion of the problem of evil by raising the problem of natural evil -- the problem of evil which is not directly caused by human free choices. At first glance, this sort of evil does not seem to be explicable by the free will defense, since this sort of evil does not seem to be explained simply by the good of our having free will. However, many proponents of the free will defense think that even natural evil can be explained in terms of free will. Here are some of the ways in which this might work:
However, this assumption about free will is one that Sider challenges in the reading we did for class today. To see this, we will need to get a bit clearer about what it means for an action to be determined. Sider expresses the thesis of determinism as the claim that “every event has a cause.” But what does it mean for an event to have a cause? What the determinist means is something like this: take any event, E. E has a cause; so, there must be some set of conditions, C, which obtained prior to E, and made E happen. What this means is that this set of prior to conditions C guarantees that E will obtain; it is impossible for C to obtain, and not be followed by E. Let’s think about an example. Let E = the event of a match catching fire. What might C be? Well, part of C is certainly that the match was struck -- that a certain amount of friction was generated by moving the match in a certain way, which raises the temperature of the surface of the match, which contains some chemical, say yellow phosphorus. Suppose that this is all that we include in C. Does C guarantee that E will happen? It seems not: it is possible, surely, that the laws of nature could have been different enough that the temperature generated was not sufficient to cause the combustion of yellow phosphorus. So we need to include in C not only some facts about events which preceded E, but also some general facts about the laws of nature in our world. Determinism is the thesis that for any event E, we can find some combination C of prior events and laws of nature which make E happen, and guarantee that E will be the case.
Sider suggests that belief in determinism is made reasonable by reflection on scientific progress. Why does he think this? What does determinism have to do with free will? As Sider says, “the threat to freedom comes when we realize that this march will eventually overtake us .” That is, the threat to freedom comes from the fact that the determinist thesis includes within its scope events such as my deciding to come to class today, which I take to be free actions of mine. Let E be the event of my deciding to come to class today. If determinism is true, there is some set of conditions C1 prior to my deciding to come to class today which guaranteed that I would decide to come to class. Furthermore, this set of conditions must itself be determined by some prior set of conditions, C2. We can continue this line of reasoning until we reach a set of conditions C100, all of which occurred prior to my birth (plus some facts about the laws of nature). But surely C100, being before my birth, is not something about which I have any choice. But if this is right, then we have the following plausible line of argument: I do not have a free choice about whether C100 happened. C100 guarantees that C99 will happen. C99 guarantees that C98 will happen. ..... C2 guarantees that C1 will happen. C1 guarantees that E will happen.
I did not have a free choice about whether E would happen. It seems that we can use a parallel argument to show that any supposedly free action is not, in fact, free. So it seems that if determinism is true, there can be no such thing as free will. (For parallel argument, see Sider’s discussion on pp. 115-6.)
To state this argument, let ‘DINOSAUR’ stand for the state of the universe during some time when dinosaurs roamed the earth, and let ‘DECISION’ stand for my decision to not sing the Notre Dame fight song 10 minutes from now.
C. I have no choice about whether DECISION will happen. (6,7,8,9) The argument is valid, and each of the premises look pretty plausible. But if each of the premises are true, then this argument shows that free will and determinism are incompatible, since we can use this argument to show, assuming the truth of determinism, that any action is unfree. (You might also want to think about how this argument could be reformulated as a reductio of the claims that determinism is true and we have free will.)
Let’s suppose we find one of these arguments is convincing, and hence that we believe that free will and determinism cannot both be true. This view is called incompatibilism , since it is the view that free will and determinism are incompatible. By itself, incompatibilism does not tell us whether determinism is true, or whether we have free will. It just says that we can’t have both. Let’s suppose that we are convinced that every event does have a cause, in Sider’s sense, and hence that every state of the universe plus the laws of nature determine every later state of the universe. Then if we are incompatibilists, we will have to give up our belief that we have free will. This is the view that Sider calls hard determinism. Hard determinism is a difficult view to accept, for at least two reasons:
Sider gives another argument against libertarianism, which is based on a conflict he sees between libertarianism and science. Here is what he says: What is the argument here? Is this a worry for the libertarian?
Sider thinks that at this point we should see that both hard determinism and libertarianism face problems. The way out of these problems, he suggests, is to believe in both free will and determinism. This, of course, involves giving up on incompatibilism, the view that there is a conflict between free will and determinism. On a compatibilist view (which Sider calls ‘soft determinism’) an action of mine might be free even though it was guaranteed to happen by facts outside my control. How could this be? How could it be determined by factors outside of my control that I will do something, and yet that act be free? Here is an example designed to convince you that this sort of thing is possible, due to the American philosopher Harry Frankfurt: “Suppose someone --- Black, let us say --- wants Jones to perform a certain action. Black is prepared to go to considerable lengths to get his way, but he prefers to avoid showing his hand unnecessarily. So he waits until Jones is about to make up his mind what to do, and does nothing unless it is clear to him (Black is an excellent judge of such things) that Jones is going to decide to do something other than what he wants him to do. If it does become clear that Jones is going to decide to do something else, Black takes effective steps to ensure that Jones decides to do, and that he does do, what he wants him to do.... Now suppose that Black never has to show his hand because Jones, for reasons of his own, decides to perform and does perform the very action Black wants him to perform. In that case, it seems clear, Jones will bear precisely the same moral responsibility for what he does as he would have borne is Black had not been ready to take steps to ensure that he do it. It would be quite unreasonable to excuse Jones for his action ... on the basis of the fact that he could not have done otherwise. This fact played no role at all in leading him to act as he did.... Indeed, everything happened just as it would have happened without Black's presence in the situation and without his readiness to intrude into it.” This seems to be a situation in which Jones’ action is free, despite the fact that factors outside of his control guaranteed that he would perform that action. But if this is possible, doesn’t this just show that incompatibilism is false?