


















































Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Prepare for your exams
Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points to download
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Community
Ask the community for help and clear up your study doubts
Discover the best universities in your country according to Docsity users
Free resources
Download our free guides on studying techniques, anxiety management strategies, and thesis advice from Docsity tutors
The challenges of achieving gender equality in criminal justice, highlighting the differences in crime statistics, police responses, and prison facilities for men and women. It explores the historical context of separate treatment for women and the need for individualized inquiry rather than gender-based categories.
What you will learn
Typology: Lecture notes
1 / 58
This page cannot be seen from the preview
Don't miss anything!
STEPHEN J. SCHULHOFERt
INTRODUCTION
t Julius Kreeger Professor of Law and Criminology and Director of the Center for Studies in Criminal Justice, University of Chicago. Portions of this Article were presented at McGeorge Law School in November 1994, at the Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association in September 1994, and at the University of Chicago Law School in November 1993 as the Wilbur G. Katz Lecture. Research for this Article was supported by the RussellJ. Parsons Faculty Research Fund and the Sonnenschein Fund at the University of Chicago Law School. I have also benefited from the research assistance of Kimberly Dunn and Katharine Moir, and from the comments of Kathryn Abrams, Albert Alschuler, Mary Coombs, Anne Coughlin, Deborah Denno, Joshua Dressler, Leslie Goldstein, Elena Kagan, Dan Kahan, Jane Larson, Larry Lessig, Dorothy Roberts, Cass Sunstein, Michael Vitiello,Joan Williams, and Laurie Wohl.
2152 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 143: 2151
Yet drawing categorical distinctions between men and women undermines our ideals. This is the familiar debate concerning sameness versus difference. It pervades discussions of gender in other areas of the law (^) and discussions of equal treatment for racial minorities, the handicapped, and other groups. The debate plays out with some unexpected twists in criminal justice. A second dilemma is that we want to be sensitive to the nuances of context when gender issues are at stake. But effective protection of women also requires that women have clear-cut rights protected by clear rules. This is the old debate concerning rules versus discretion. Again, it plays out with some unexpected (^) twists in criminal justice. A third dilemma concerns the limits of theory. We need theory to help pinpoint the problems confronting women and to help organize thinking about solutions. But theory is not up to the task. Indeed, I will argue that in criminal justice, theory can never be equal to the task. Much of contemporary feminist discussion and scholarship center on developing new theories or on parsing the differences among theories and defending commitments to one of them or another. One theory emphasizes formally equal treatment.^2 A major competitor is a theory stressing the ways that culture and social practice subordinate women under laws that are formally neutral.' A third theory emphasizes context, caring, and connec- tion in lieu of what it views as a "male" commitment to abstract rights defined without regard to context. 4 One scholar has iden-
1 See, e.g., MARTHA MINOW, MAKING ALL THE DIFFERENCE: INCLUSION, EXCLUSION, AND AMERICAN LAW 21 (1990) ("The dilemma of difference grows from the ways in which this society assigns individuals to categories and, on that basis, determines whom to include in and whom to exclude from political, social, and economic activities."). 2 See, e.g., Wendy W. Williams, The Equality Crisis: Some Reflections on Culture, Courts, and Feminism, 7 WOMEN'S RTS. L. REP. 175, 175 (1982) (stating that courts should "rule that the privileges the law explicitly bestows on men must also be made available to women"); Wendy W. Williams, Notesfrom a First Generation, 1989 U. CHI. LEGAL F. 99, 99 (identifying the "'formal' equality" approach as "an insistence that laws not embody explicit sex-based distinctions"). 3 See, e.g., CATHARINE A. MACKINNON, FEMINISM (^) UNMODIFIED: DISCOURSES ON LIFE AND LAW 40 (1987) (discussing the "dominance approach" to the equality question); Christine A. Littleton, ReconstructingSexual Equality, 75 CAL. L. REV. 1279, 1282-84 (1987) (noting that courts routinely apply "phallocentric standards 'equally' to men and women's different reproductive biology or economic position to yield... unequal results for women"). 4 See, e.g., CAROL GILLIGAN, (^) IN A DIFFERENT VOICE: PSYCHOLOGICAL (^) THEORY AND
2154 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 143: 2151
search for a feminism that can guide reform in criminal justice and, perhaps, other areas. Despite the undoubted importance of theoretical insight, the most effective tools of reform at the present juncture are likely to be eclectic and atheoretical, and the most effective feminist scholarship is likely to be one that attends to the complexities of specific institutions and procedures. What is needed, I suggest, is a feminism of particulars, a recog- nition that real solutions are likely to lie deeply embedded in the details.
I. WHY CRIMINAL LAW IS "MALE"
The criminal justice system fits almost perfectly Lincoln's conception of a government of the people, by the people, and for the people. It fits perfectly, if you are willing to equate "the people" with the male half of the population. Criminal law is-and has been for centuries-a system of rules conceived and enforced by men, for men, and against men. There are counterexamples but not many. The law against pros- titution, which might make sense as a way to protect young and poor women from sexual exploitation, is not enforced that way. It is enforced almost exclusively against women.^8 The law notices women but prosecutes those it should be protecting. In many instances law enforcement does benefit and protect women. But overwhelmingly, criminal law is designed and implemented with men in mind. This observation should be considered completely uncontroversial. One way for the reader to confirm its accuracy is simply to pause for a moment and attempt to picture a typical offender. What does he look like? He is inevitably the subject of the inquiry. The criminal offender is disproportionately male, overwhelmingly so. In 1983, men and boys, 49% of the U.S.
(^8) See e.g., RICHARD SYMANSKI, THE IMMORAL LANDSCAPE: FEMALE PROSTITUTION
IN WESTERN SOCIETIES 88 (1981) (noting that although New York law was changed in 1964 to criminalize both male prostitution and the act of patronizinga prostitute, the effect of the change was minimal; in 1977, the number of males arrested was less than one-tenth the number of females arrested). Recent attention to the need for sanctioning prostitutes' customers has not substantially changed this picture. See Eleanor M. Miller et al., The United States, in PROSTITUTION: AN INTERNATIONAL HANDBOOK ON TRENDS, PROBLEMS, AND POLICIES 300, 313 (Nanette J. Davis ed., 1993) (noting the persistence of arrest patterns in which 70% of prostitution arrests are of females, while male customers account for only about 10% of arrests).
THE FEMINIST CHALLENGE
9
9 See BUREAU OF JUSTICE STATISTICS, U.S. DEP'T OF JUSTICE, REPORT TO THE NATION ON CRIME AND JUSTICE 41 (2d ed. 1988) [hereinafter REPORT TO THE NATION]. 10 See S. REP. No. 197, 102d Cong., 1st Sess. 33 (1991) ("Women bear the disproportionate burden of some of the most pernicious crimes, like rape, and some of the most persistent crimes, like beatings in the home."); S. REP. No. 545, 101st Cong., 2d Sess. 30-31 (1990) (noting "a spiralling 'gender gap' of violence... [in which] female victimization is increasing faster than male victimization (at least for some crimes)" (citations omitted)). " See BUREAU OF JUSTICE STATISTICS, U.S. DEP'T OF JUSTICE, CRIMINAL VICTIM- IZATION 1991, at 6 (1992) [hereinafter VICTIMIZATION IN 1991]. 12 In measuring domestic violence, a number of surveys suggest that male partners are victimized at about the same rate as female partners. See MURRAY A. STRAUS ET AL., BEHIND CLOSED DOORS: VIOLENCE IN THE AMERICAN FAMILY 266 (1980) (reporting a rate of 12.0 for husband-to-wife violence compared to a rate of 11.5 for wife-to-husband violence); Murray A. Straus & RichardJ. Gelles, Societal Change and Change in Family Violence from 1975 to 1985: As Revealed by Two National Surveys, 48 J. MARRIAGE & FAM. 465, 470 (1986) (reporting that in 1985, the rate of husband-to- wife violence was 113 per 1000 couples, while the rate of wife-to-husband violence was 121 per 1000 couples). But the overall data on the rates of assault by victim gender present a misleading picture because the assaults experienced by male victims tend to be concentrated disproportionately in the milder forms of slapping or hit- ting; the female partners are much more likely to suffer the most serious assaults. See Irene H. Frieze & Angela Browne, Violence in Marriage, in FAMILY VIOLENCE 163, 181 (Michael Tonry (^) & Norval Morris eds., 1989) (noting that "the average number of severely violent assaults by a husband against a nonviolent wife was three times greater than the average number of wives' assaults on nonviolent husbands").
19 On the possibility that women's independence and increased workforce partici- pation might increase women's rates of offending, see infra text accompanying (^) notes 125-29. For a discussion of connections between women's independence and society's stereotypes of women as criminals, see Susan N. Herman, Thelma and Louise and Bonnie andJean: Images of Women as Criminals, 2 S. CAL. (^) REV. L. & WOMEN'S STUD. 53, 62 (1992); Elizabeth V. Spelman & Martha Minow, Outlaw Women: An Essay (^) on Thelma and Louise, 26 NEw ENG. L. REv. 1281, 1281 (1992).
2157
2158 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 143: 2151
II. DOMESTIC VIOLENCE
Lack of attention to domestic violence has a venerable tradition in the criminal justice system. Failure to prosecute abusive husbands was not just the result of inattention, because for centuries, the criminal law gave the husband an affirmative privilege to beat his wife in order to provide her with what was (^) seen as appropriate chastisement and instruction." The husband's formal privilege of chastisement was abolished by the end (^) of the nineteenth century,^21 but wife beating continued. The extent of it cannot be measured (^) precisely, but even the cautious studies point to high levels of abuse: 28% of all women experiencing a violent assault at some point in their marriages; 16% of married women assaulted by a spouse in^ a^ single^ year.
22
This culture of spousal abuse coexists with a police practice of not arresting wife beaters, especially in cases perceived as "ordinary" misdemeanor assaults. 2 1 Many episodes of domestic violence involve life-threatening attacks, assaults with guns, knives, (^) and other weapons, or brutal battering that leaves serious (^) physical injuries. Police are likely to take such cases more (^) seriously than the much
" See Anne M. Coughlin, Excusing Women, 82 CAL. L. REV. 1, 40-41 (1994) (noting that the husband's right to chastise his wife stemmed from "the belief that married women suffered from a volitional disability");Joyce E. McConnell, Beyond Metaphor: Battered Women, Involuntary Servitude and the Thirteenth Amendment, 4 YALE J.L. & FEMINISM 207, 232 (1992) (noting that "[t]he batterer's belief in a man's right to chastise his partner and to coerce sexual services remains entrenched in the law"). Blackstone attempted to rationalize the husband's privilege of chastisement by connectingit to the marital coercion doctrine, under which a husband could be liable for crimes the wife might commit in his presence (actual or constructive). It was only fitting, Blackstone argued, that the husband have a corresponding privilege of chastisement in order to deter his wife from actions that would expose him to criminal liability. See 1 WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES (^432) ("For, as he is to answer for her misbehaviour, the law thought it reasonable to intrust him with (^) this power of restraining her, by domestic chastisement, in the same moderation that a man is allowed to correct his servants or children .... "). " See, e.g., Fulgham v. State, 46 Ala. 143, 143 (1871) (abolishing a husband's right to chastise his wife); The Queen v.Jackson, (^) 1 Q.B. 671,681-82 (1891) (abolishing the right of marital chastisement in England); see also Bernadette D. Sewell, (^) Note, History of Abuse: Societa4 (^) Judicia, and Legislative Responses to the Problem of Wife Beating, 23 SUFFOLK U. L. REV. 983, 984 (1989) (noting that legal authorization of marital chastisement "continued to exist in many Western cultures until the late nineteenth century"). ' See Frieze & Browne, supra note 12, at 179. 2 See LAWRENCE W. SHERMAN, POLICING DOMESTIC VIOLENCE: EXPERIMENTS AND DILEMMAS 26-27 (1992) (describing (^) patterns of underenforcement of domestic violence laws).
2160 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 143: 2151
A. Mandatory Arrest Through the Lens of FeministJurisprudence
Domestic violence, a central issue in the struggle to assure dignity and equality for women, is extensively discussed in feminist literature.-" Yet there has been little (^) effort to consider how battles over theoretical commitments or attempts to refine theoretical paradigms (^) might inform efforts to begin solving this critical problem. One obvious irony involves the manner in which the tactic favored by many feminist reformers (mandatory arrest) collides with the part of feminist theory that advocates open-textured standards and attention to the nuances of relationships. Feminists inspired by the work of Carol Gilligan (^32) reject inflexible rights as a distinctively male conception. 3 Police officers who do not arrest battering husbands are not being very "male" in that sense. They are making ad hoc judgments, based on their intuitions about the whole situation. This sort of police discretion is presumably not what Gilligan really meant by an ethic of care and connection. Nevertheless, (^) the example highlights a more general point about the supposed clash between a male ethic of rights and (^) a female ethic of context and relationship. There is (^) nothing especially feminist about an ad hoc, discretionary approach (^) to making decisions. It all depends on the values that inform the exercise of the discretion. Nor should (^) we automatically count as "feminist" any ethic that emphasizes (^) caring, connection, and the continuity of relationships. There are situa- tions where that ethic is not only out of place, but dangerous to women. 34 Everything depends on the particular problem, the
arrest policies instituted in New York City). For references to the recent literature, see SANFORD H. KADISH & STEPHENJ. SCHULHOFER, CRIMINAL LAW AND ITS PROCESSEs 829 & n.2 (6th ed. 1995). 32 See, e.g., GILLIGAN, supra note 4. 3 See, (^) e.g., M. Kay Harris, Moving into (^) the New Millennium: Toward a (^) Feminist Vision ofJustice, (^) PRISONJ., Fall-Winter 1987, at 27,32 ("[In Gilligan's research] [m]en were more likely to employ a 'rights/justice' orientation [toward moral (^) issues] and women were more likely to reflect a 'care/response' orientation ... ."); Frances Heidensohn, Models ofJustice: PortiaorPersephone?Some (^) Thoughts on Equality, Fairness and Gender in the Field of CriminalJustice, 14 INT'L J. Soc. L. 287, (^) 295-96 (1986) (noting that men become "detached, autonomous and individualized" in their quest for justice, while women tend to focus on context and caring). ' An "ethic of care" poses related (^) dangers in such criminaljustice contexts as the juvenile court movement, civil commitment of the mentally ill, and rehabilitative models of sentencing. See StephenJ. Schulhofer, The GenderQuestion (^) in CriminalLaw, SOC. (^) PHIL. & POL'Y, Spring 1990, at 105, 124. In particular,
the model of caring and connection [is flawed] because ... conflicting interests are inherent in^ any^ criminal^ justice^ system^ that^ serves^ society's interests in deterrence and social protection. A system of^ criminal^ law premised on caring and connection will simply mask conflict and invite the abuses that vague standards of intervention have produced over and over in ostensibly benign programs. Id. (citation omitted). " Kathleen Daly, CriminalJusticeIdeologies and Practices in Different Voices: Some Feminist Questions About Justice, 17 INT'LJ. Soc. L. 1. 2 (1989). m See, e.g., MACKINNON, supra note 3, at 41 (noting that in domestic relationships, battery of women tends to be ignored, whereas "[w]hen [men] are hit, a person has been assaulted"). 17 See (^) id. at 76 (arguing that when government (^) refuses to prosecute for (^) marital rape, "the woman's obligation to deliver sexually is effectively enforced by the state").
Understandingthe Problem, Forgingthe Solutions, in FEMINIST JURISPRUDENCE 188, 202 (PatriciaSmith ed., 1993)^ (arguing^ that^ "[a]rrest^ of^ the^ batterer^ is^ the^ central^ element of an effective police response"); Zorza, supra note 28, at 66 (arguing that in order to deter batterers effectively, more^ severe^ sanctions^ should be imposed).
participation in the follow-ups, and the follow-up^ study^ was^ limited^ to^ only^ six months, a period when temporary deterrence^ effects^ may^ dominate^ to^ the^ extent^ that court proceedings remain^ possible.^ See^ Elliott,^ supra^ note^ 25,^ at^453 (noting^ that^ only 49% of the victims in the Minneapolis study completed all^12 follow-up^ interviews). 44 See SHERMAN, supra note 23, at 15-18 (reporting results from similar experi- ments conducted in Omaha, Charlotte, Milwaukee, Colorado Springs, and Miami). 45 See id. at 17, 188-87 (describing an initial deterrent effect of arrest, followed by a subsequent escalation in the likelihood of repeat violence in Omaha, Charlotte, and Milwaukee). 46 In Minneapolis, the deterrent effects of arrest (measured by victim interviews) decayed over time and disappeared after six months. See id. at^ 197.^ Although^ the Minneapolis study did not collect victim interview data after six months, the trend of the data suggests the possibility of an escalation effect after the six-month point. (When repeat violence was^ measured^ by^ official^ arrest^ records,^ arrest^ had^ a^ clear deterrent effect^ that^ continued^ for^ the^ entire^ 18-month^ period studied.^ See^ id.^ But official records may present a misleading picture^ of^ the^ actual^ level^ of^ battering,^ if arrest deters victims^ from^ reporting^ subsequent^ incidents^ to^ the^ police.) 47 Zorza, (^) supra note (^) 28, at 66.
1995]^2163
2164 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 143: 2151
him.^48 And there is some indication that visible, highly popular mandatory arrest programs have permitted legislators to reduce their support for more costly solutions like shelters for battered women.
49 Surprisingly, the tentative Minneapolis study and its recommen- dations for a more punitive approach received widespread attention and an immediately favorable reception, but public officials and the media have either attacked or ignored the more thorough studies that suggest the opposite conclusion." Theoretical^ and^ ideological commitments to punitive strategies and to a rights-oriented response to aggression seem to dominate any concern for designing operational programs which actually help abused women. Yet the best available evidence suggests that an across-the-board policy of mandatory arrest should be anathema^ to feminists.^ As^ Lawrence Sherman writes, using mandatory arrest to fight domestic violence "may make as much sense as fighting fire with gasoline." 51
C. Selective Mandatory Arrest?
An important qualification to this pessimistic assessment of mandatory arrest emerges when data from the follow-up studies are disaggregated. The escalation effect seems especially strong when the batterer is unemployed, but arrest does appear to have a net deterrent effect when the husband has ajob or other marks of^ social stability.^5 2 That finding triggers a further series of dilemmas. Should we arrest only the employed? If not, should we arrest in all cases, knowing that this will harm some women? A third possibility is to leave the decision to each officer on the spot. That would probably give us the worst of both worlds: police would arrest blacks and the underclass while^ letting^ off^ middle-class^ white
48 In Connecticut, mandatory arrest policies reportedly led to the arrest of^ both spouses in 14% of the cases. See Jan Hoffman, When Men Hit Women, N.Y. TIMEs, Feb. 16, 1992, (Magazine), at 23,26. Moreover, if children are present and no other caretaker for them is available, the children may have to be placed in state custody until one of the parents is released. See id. 49 See (^) SHERMAN, supra (^) note 23, at 255. 'o See id. at 135-36 (describing political attacks on empirical research and the unwillingness of the Wisconsin legislature to repeal its mandatory^ arrest^ statute^ after the Milwaukee study had indicated the harmful effects of that policy); id. at 266 (describing sparse press coverage of the Milwaukee findings); Sherman & Cohn, supra note 41, at 129 (stating that publicity about the Minneapolis study reached a large number of police departments and had a substantial influence on policy). 51 SHERMAN, supra note 23, at 210. 52 See id. at 155.
2166 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 143: 2151
D. Getting Tougher: Giving Content to "Arrest"
Instead of seeking to minimize arrest, especially for unemployed
severe sanctions for all categories of offenders. Indeed, mandatory arrest may appear ineffective or dangerous in part because the response being advocated ("arrest") is mainly a slogan, not a fully specified policy. In many cities, suspects arrested on domestic violence charges are free within a few hours; among the six cities in which mandatory arrest experiments were conducted, average times in custody varied from twenty-four hours to only two.^5 " The constitutional right to bail" accounts for some of the rapid release times and may make that feature of the current landscape difficult to change. Nonetheless, rapid release times probably are not a major cause of the ineffectiveness of mandatory arrest, because most of the experiments show some deterrence over the short run, even when suspects spent very little time in jail.^59 The problem is that the deterrence effect of arrest tends to dissipate, and escalation effects begin to dominate, roughly six months after the arrest.^6 " The decay of deterrence effects could be slowed by making the initial arrest a more unpleasant experience, but that approach obviously risks making the escalation effects more severe as well. There is another reason why mandatory arrest is primarily a slogan, not a concrete policy. To advocate "arrest" says nothing about what should happen after the arrestee's inevitable release on recognizance or money bail. Husbands arrested for misdemeanor assault are almost never prosecuted.^6 ' An obvious option is to combine the increased use of arrest with a greater determination to get convictions and jail time. But the available data permit little confidence that prosecution provides the easy answer. In Milwau- kee and Charlotte, two cities in which mandatory arrest appeared to produce an escalation effect, the percentage of suspects prosecuted
57 See SHERMAN, supra note (^) 23, at 140-42. Longer times (^) in custody did not correlate cleanly with either the deterrence effects or the escalation effects, perhaps because times were poorly measured, and other factors that affect the severity of the arrest experience (jail conditions, for example) were not measured at all. See id. 59 "^ See^ U.S.^ CONST.^ amend.^ VIII. See SHERMAN, supra note 23, at 129, 141. 60 See id. at 189. 6" See Sherman, supra note 42, at 29 (reporting that in Minneapolis, only 4% of those arrested were ever convicted, and in Milwaukee, only 1% were ever convicted).
E. Other Alternatives
62See SHERMAN, supra note 23, at 141-42. s See id.; Franklyn W. Dunford et al., The Role of Arrest in Domestic Assault: The Omaha Police Experiment, 28 CRIMINOLOGY 183, 193 (1990). " See supra text accompanying note 52. 6 See SHERMAN, supra note 23, at 249 (noting that "no randomized experiment yet demonstrat[es] (^) that court-ordered counseling can reduce the frequency or prevalence of repeat domestic violence"); Zorza, (^) supra note 28, at 67 (noting that "completing batterer treatment made no difference in stopping future violence"). 6See Zorza, supra note 28, at 67 (suggesting that victims may be "deceived" into
7071 See See Sherman id. at 7, 12. & Berk, supra note 27, at 7, 9.
2170 UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 143: 2151
at some risk to the women we are trying to help. A more useful rule of thumb, therefore, would not insist on arrest per se, but mandatory action-action of some sort, from a list of strong, constructive alternatives,^7 2 and a mandatory report (normally (^) in writing), both to ensure a thoughtful response and (^) to inform officers who might be called to the same address (^) in the future. Specific response (^) options will necessarily reflect the services and programs (including prosecution programs) available in the particular jurisdiction; over the longer run, effort should focus on strengthening and evaluating alternative approaches. For chronic offenders and cases involving serious injuries, a vigorous prosecu- tion program should assure substantial jail or prison terms. In the most minor cases, a stern warning or a reference to counseling may be appropriate, especially if records are adequate to (^) assure that there have been no prior episodes of violence involving the same couple. For cases falling in between these extremes, arrest or some other means of separating the parties should be considered, with choices depending on the woman's desire to preserve the relation- ship, the history of past abuse, and other relevant circumstances. Where resources and back-up procedures permit, it may be appropriate to require the husband to leave and stay away long enough for the wife to obtain an effective order of protection. But if that avenue seems unlikely to afford real safety for the woman, (^) an offer to transport her to a shelter may be appropriate, if that is the course she prefers. The spousal-abuse problem illustrates two general points that apply to criminal justice and to probably most other areas of the legal system. First, legal, social, and institutional details are critical. Second, quick-fix statutes and doctrinal change do very little, and may even backfire, unless they are backed by changes in attitudes, personnel, and resources.
III. RAPE
I have just suggested that rigid rules will not work well in domestic violence cases. There, we need to rely on flexible standards. For rape statutes, I reach the opposite conclusion.
7 See SHERMAN, supra note 23, at 253-56 (listing options including transporting the victim to a shelter, taking the suspect or victim to a detoxification treatment center, and allowing the victim to decide if an immediate arrest should be made).