Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

The Assertion-Status of 'God Exists': A Verificationist Perspective, Lecture notes of Theology

The assertion-status of the statement 'God exists' from a verificationist perspective. The author, Hick, argues that 'God exists' is an assertion based on its entailment of eschatological predictions that are in principle verifiable. Nielsen challenges Hick's argument, claiming that the predictions contain essential references to 'God' and thus create a circular argument. The document also discusses Nielsen's other criticisms of Hick's position.

What you will learn

  • How does Nielsen criticize Hick's use of the verification principle?
  • What is Hick's argument for the assertion-status of 'God exists'?
  • Why does Nielsen claim that Hick's argument involves a circular argument?

Typology: Lecture notes

2021/2022

Uploaded on 09/27/2022

floweryy
floweryy 🇬🇧

4.7

(16)

251 documents

1 / 7

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
Eschatological Verification and
Parontological Obfuscation
JAMES C.
S.
WERNHAM
T
HE
PURPOSE
OF
THIS
PAPER
is
to comment
upon
the debate between
Nielsen
and
Mavrodes
on
Hick's use of the concept of eschatological
verification.1 I have chosen to examine
that
debate,
not
because I believe
it
to be a good one,
but
because I believe
it
to be a good example of a
bad
one.
It
is a
bad
one, partly because most of the points made by the
contributors are wrong,
and
partly because the issue which
is
raised
and
stated with reasonable clarity by Hick
is
progressively obfuscated
in
the
course of the discussion. I propose to ignore the minor errors of mis-
understanding
and
misrepresentation which have no crucial bearing upon
the central issue
under
discussion,
and
to ignore also the snide asides by
Nielsen about the distinguished theologians whom he does not profess to
understand. I shall
be
content to take note of his
major
misunderstandings
of the theologian whom
he
does profess to understand.
The
question raised by Hick
is
whether those religious utterances which
have all the appearance of being assertions really are assertions.
Part
of
his purpose is to reject,
and
give reason for rejecting, the claim of some
that
they are not.2
In
particular, his contention is
that
"God
exists,"
spoken of the Christian God,
is
an
assertion.
The
assumption underlying
his
paper
is
that
an
utterance is
an
assertion if
it
is
in principle verifiable,
and
his concern, therefore,
is
to show
that
"God
exists," said of the
Christian God,
is
in principle verifiable. Although his underlying assump-
tion
is
made clear in the course of his paper,
it
(reasonably)
is
not there
defended;
and
the same
is
true of the sense which
he
gives to the term
verification. His claim is
that
"God
exists"3 entails predictions about
matters eschatological which are
in
principle verifiable, albeit only escha-
tologically.
The
predictions which he holds to be entailed by
"God
exists" are stated,
and
the experiences are described which, if they were
to occur, would,
in
his view, verify
them
and
it.
Being clear about
what
the issue
is,
we should also be clear about
what
it_
1.
Cf. CJT, 9
(1963),
271-81;
10
(1964),
187-91;
11
(1965),
135-41.
For
Rick's
paper
see
John
Hick
(ed.),
The
Existence
of
God
(New
York:
Macmillan, 1964),
pp.
253-74.
2.
E.g. R.
M.
Hare,
in
his contribution
to
the
discussion of "Theology
and
Falsifica-
tion." in A. Flew
and
A.
MacIntyre
(eds.),
New Essays in Philosophical Theology
(London: S.C.M. Press, 1955),
pp.
99-103;
R.
B.
Braithwaite,
An
Empiricist's View
of
the Nature
of
Religious Belief
(Cambridge:
University Press, 1955);
reprinted
in
Hick
(ed.),
Th·e
Existence
of
God,
pp.
229-52).
3.
Throughout,
it
is
to
be understood
that
"God
exists"
is
short
for
"
'God
exists'
said of the Christian
God."
50
CANADIAN
JOURNAL
OF
THEOLOGY,
Vol.
XIII
( 1967), No. 1
pf3
pf4
pf5

Partial preview of the text

Download The Assertion-Status of 'God Exists': A Verificationist Perspective and more Lecture notes Theology in PDF only on Docsity!

Eschatological Verification and

Parontological Obfuscation

JAMES C. S. WERNHAM

T

HE PURPOSE OF THIS PAPER is to comment upon the debate between Nielsen and Mavrodes on Hick's use of the concept of eschatological verification. 1 I have chosen to examine that debate, not because I believe it to be a good one, but because I believe it to be a good example of a bad one. It is a bad one, partly because most of the points made by the contributors are wrong, and partly because the issue which is raised and stated with reasonable clarity by Hick is progressively obfuscated in the course of the discussion. I propose to ignore the minor errors of mis- understanding and misrepresentation which have no crucial bearing upon the central issue under discussion, and to ignore also the snide asides by Nielsen about the distinguished theologians whom he does not profess to understand. I shall be content to take note of his major misunderstandings of the theologian whom he does profess to understand. The question raised by Hick is whether those religious utterances which have all the appearance of being assertions really are assertions. Part of his purpose is to reject, and give reason for rejecting, the claim of some that they are not.^2 In particular, his contention is that "God exists," spoken of the Christian God, is an assertion. The assumption underlying his paper is that an utterance is an assertion if it is in principle verifiable, and his concern, therefore, is to show that "God exists," said of the Christian God, is in principle verifiable. Although his underlying assump- tion is made clear in the course of his paper, it (reasonably) is not there defended; and the same is true of the sense which he gives to the term verification. His claim is that "God exists"^3 entails predictions about matters eschatological which are in principle verifiable, albeit only escha- tologically. The predictions which he holds to be entailed by "God exists" are stated, and the experiences are described which, if they were to occur, would, in his view, verify them and it. Being clear about what the issue is, we should also be clear about what it_

  1. Cf. CJT, 9 (1963), 271-81; 10 (1964), 187-91; 11 (1965), 135-41. For Rick's paper see John Hick (ed.), The Existence of God (New York: Macmillan, 1964), pp. 253-74.
  2. E.g. R. M. Hare, in his contribution to the discussion of "Theology and Falsifica- tion." in A. Flew and A. MacIntyre (eds.), New Essays in Philosophical Theology (London: S.C.M. Press, 1955), pp. 99-103; R. B. Braithwaite, An Empiricist's View of the Nature of Religious Belief (Cambridge: University Press, 1955); reprinted in Hick (ed.), Th·e Existence of God, pp. 229-52).
  3. Throughout, it is to be understood that "God exists" is short for " 'God exists' said of the Christian God." 50 CANADIAN JOURNAL OF THEOLOGY, Vol. XIII ( 1967), No. 1

VERIFICATION AND OBFUSCATION 51

is not. The question is not, as Nielsen correctly observes/ whether "God exists" is true; it is whether "God exists" is an assertion. It is not, in other words, about the truth-value of "God exists," but, as Hick puts it in a passage which Nielsen misquotes, about its assertion-status. 5 More important, at least for the progress of the debate, the question is not, as Nielsen sometimes says that it is, whether theistic claims are intelligible or whether religious utterances can be understood. Commands, ejaculations, and all sorts of expressions which are not assertions are certainly intelligible and under- stood. The question is whether "God exists" is an assertion rather than a command or ejaculation or resolution or anything else, intelligible or unintelligible. I have not said, nor do I wish to suggest, that Nielsen never gets the issue right. Often he does. But sometimes he does not; and, regrettably for the course of the debate, it is the issue as mis-stated by him which is taken up and commented upon by Mavrodes. It is not difficult to see just how Nielsen gets off the right rails. In the opening paragraph of his paper he affirms that Rick's concern is with the question "whether it is intelligible to claim that divine existence is a fact" ;^6 and he emphasizes the word "intelligible" by putting it in italics. His purpose in so doing is, of course, to distinguish the question of the truth of "God exists" from the question of its intelligibility as an asser- tion. But the introduction of the word "intelligible" operates as a kind of railway switch and we are off on the wrong track in the next paragraph but one when the saving reference to "fact" is dropped off and we are told that Rick's question is whether theistic claims are intelligible.^7 That is not Rick's question; it is that, however, which Mavrodes, misled by Nielsen, takes to be Rick's question. But more of that later. Nielsen's central argument against Hick is stated in section n of his paper and culminates in the verdict that "Hick is asking us to pull our- selves up by our own bootstraps."^8 The question whether that verdict is a justified one needs to be examined, but a decision on it requires first a reasonably precise formulation of Rick's argument. Central to that argument is the claim that "God exists" entails predictions of an escha- tological nature, and part of his paper is concerned with stating what these are. It will not, I think, be a distortion of his thought if we take them to be as follows: first, that some time there will exist that quality of life which the New Testament calls eternal life and which Hick describes, tentatively, as final self-fulfillment and happiness; and, second, that Jesus will reign in this kingdom of final self-fulfillment and happiness.^9 Implicit in his case is, of course, the claim that both of these predic- tions are in principle verifiable. Let us call them a and b. Rick's argument

  1. Cf. K. Nielsen, "Eschatological Verification," CJT, 9 (1963), 271.
  2. Cf. Hick (ed.), The Existence of God, p. 261; CJT, 9 (1963), 272.
  3. Cf. Nielsen, "Eschatological Verification," 271.
    1. Cf. Ibid.
  4. Ibid., 276.
    1. Cf. Hick (ed.), The Existence of God, pp. 269-72.

VERIFICATION AND OBFUSCATION 53 the case falls with Rick's statement of it. Nielsen's confidence in Hick is misplaced, as is his tribute to the "care and skill" with which Hick has presented his argument.^11 Nielsen's second major complaint against Hick is stated in section m of his paper and is summed up in his statement that "questions of what is meant by X cannot possibly be settled by faith or trust." 12 Perhaps that is right, but nowhere that I can find does Hick suggest that they can. Cer- tainly he does not say so in the passage to which Nielsen refers. There he is discussing a quite different question, the question whether all or only some will share in the experiences which would constitute a post-mortem verification of the existence of God; and his suggestion is that, perhaps, only those who have faith ante mortem will have the relevant experiences post mortem. He nowhere claims that faith can be a substitute for these experi- ences. His suggestion is that possibly it may be a precondition for having them. And that, to use Nielsen's (New England?) expression, is a very different kind of chowder. Let us turn now to Mavrodes. In the introductory section of his paper Mavrodes summarizes Nielsen's central argument against Hick and con- cludes his summary with a statement which confirms that he has been misled by Nielsen into misunderstanding Rick's question. "Nielsen," he says, "there- fore concludes that Rick's attempt to show the meaningfulness of talk about God has failed." 13 But Hick, as we have seen, was not attempting to show the meaningfulness of talk about God; he was attempting to show that "God exists" is an assertion. I shall leave until later Nielsen's reply to Mavrodes' summary of his conclusion, and also his reply to Mavrodes' further complaint that "Nielsen gives us no account at all of what he means by verification."^14 I shall leave entirely without comment Mavrodes' account of the history of the verification principle, except to note that he treats the principle, not as a criterion for determining whether an utterance is an assertion ( which is what alone is relevant if we are discussing Hick), but as a criterion for "distinguishing the meaningful from the meaningless." 15 I turn, instead, to the central argument of the paper which is given in section II and is summed up in the claim that "the confusion in the response is the mirror image of the confusion in the challenge." 16 Mavrodes' complaint against Nielsen is not that he sees a circle where there is none, but that he sees only one circle where there are two. He agrees with Nielsen that Rick's procedure involves him in a circle; he complains against Nielsen that he does not see that the verificationist challenge, which Hick is attempting to meet, is itself involved in a circle. He is, I think, clearly wrong on both counts. There is no circle in Rick's

  1. Nielsen, "Eschatological Verification," 274.
  2. Ibid., 281.
  3. G. I. Mavrodes, "God and Verification," CJT, 10 (1964), 187.
  4. Ibid., 188.
  5. Ibid.
  6. Ibid., 190.
  7. Cf. ibid.

54 CANADIAN JOURNAL OF THEOLOGY case; and if that is so, it, of course, cannot be true that the circle in the response is a mirror image of the circle in the challenge. The fact is that there is no circle in the challenge either. Mavrodes' argument is as follows. The position of the verificationist is that one comes to know the meaning of an utterance ( and, therefore, that it has a meaning) by coming to know what will verify it. But one cannot, he objects, know what will verify the utterance unless one already knows the meaning of the utterance ( and, therefore, that it has a meaning). Hick, therefore, and others who accept the verificationist challenge, can say what will verify the utterance only by assuming a meaning for it ( and, therefore, that it is meaningful) , and he is, therefore, involved in a circle; for he is supposed to be showing that it is meaningful by showing that it is verifiable. If this argument were correct it would mean that, no matter how Hick formulated the predictions which he holds to be entailed by "God exists" · and to be in principle verifiable, he would be involved in a circle; for the claim is that he would have to assume a meaning for them in order to say what would verify them. Mavrodes' objection, in other words, does not tum upon the fact that Hick uses terms like "divine purpose," "Christ," "Son of God" and so on in stating the predictions. His implication is that any formulation of them would involve him in a circle; so that the defence of Hick that they can be otherwise stated does not help. But Mavrodes' argument is quite invalid as a criticism of Hick. 18 For, as has already sufficiently been pointed up, Hick is not using the verification principle as a means of determining whether "God exists" is meaningful; he is using it to determine whether "God exists" is an assertion. His position, in other words, is this. It is agreed that "God exists" is meaningful. The only question is whether it is an assertion or not. To decide that question we apply the verification principle. Either something would verify it or nothing would. If the former is the case, it is an assertion; if the latter, it is not. In that procedure there is nothing circular at all. Mavrodes' belief that there is depends upon his failure to distinguish two things: understanding an utterance and understanding that it is an assertion. And that failure depends upon a failure to distinguish between the use of the verification principle as a criterion of meaningfulness and its use as a cri- terion of assertion-status. In his second paper Nielsen makes this ( the correct) reply to Mavrodes. "Mavrodes," he says, "misses my intent and misses, I believe, Hick's intent as well" ;^19 and he proceeds to make the point that neither he nor Hick was using the verification principle as "a general criterion of meaning." 20 That is certainly correct so far as it concerns Hick's paper. It is partly correct so far as it concerns his own first one. He is right, therefore, in

  1. Despite Alastair McKinnon's endorsement of it; cf. his "Unfalsifiability and Religious Belief," CJT, 12 (1966), 118.
  2. K. Nielsen, "God and Verification Again," CJT, 11 (1965), 137.
  3. Ibid.

56 CANADIAN^ JOURNAL^ OF^ THEOLOGY is, of course, not any lack of clarity about the meaning of the term "verifi- cation"; it is the lack of clarity, shared by both Mavrodes and Nielsen, about the use to which the verification principle is being put. One must distinguish between its use as a criterion of meaningfulness tout court, its use as a criterion of cognitive meaningfulness or assertion-status, and its use as a criterion of empiricality or scientific status. Nielsen's rejoinder, there- fore, that he "assumed that we have a reasonably decent understanding of verification" 26 is in part right; for it is a refusal to get involved in an issue which is not the central one. But it is in part wrong, or at least inadequate; for it does not make clear what is the central issue and why that is not it. There was also a simpler, more obvious, and more adequate reply, which, however, he does not make: namely, that he was commenting critically on a paper by Hick, and therefore, in order to be relevant, was bound to discuss the issue on the basis of definitions provided by Hick. And whatever may be true of Nielsen's first paper, Hick certainly devotes several pages to an account of what he means by verification. I said in the beginning that my purpose was to examine the debate between Nielsen and Mavrodes. I have said where I think Nielsen is wrong. I have said where I think Mavrodes is wrong. I have said where I think Nielsen is wrong in his response to Mavrodes. I think, incidentally, that Hick is also wrong. But that is another story.

  1. Nielsen, "God and Verification Again," 135.