Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Edmund Burke's Conservative Presumption: Tradition, Deference, and the Harm Principle, Lecture notes of Law

Edmund Burke's conservative presumption, which advocates for deference to old and established traditions, laws, and moral norms. Burke's argument is based on the harm principle, which asserts that radical change imposed on a society can reduce human welfare and that moral nonconformists may cause more harm than good. The document also discusses the optimality and entrenchment theses as possible justifications for Burke's presumption.

What you will learn

  • Why does Burke advocate for deference to old traditions and moral norms?
  • How can the optimality thesis be used to justify Burke's presumption?
  • What is the harm principle in the context of Burke's conservative presumption?
  • What is Edmund Burke's conservative presumption?
  • What is the entrenchment thesis and how does it relate to Burke's presumption?

Typology: Lecture notes

2021/2022

Uploaded on 09/12/2022

mdbovary
mdbovary 🇬🇧

4.8

(8)

215 documents

1 / 15

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
1
Burkean Conservatism and the Presumption in Fav or of Tradition
At the heart of conservative political thought lies its plea for deference to the political
structure, particular laws, and moral norms of a society that are old and established. Burkean
conservatism (BC) does not oppose all soci al change, but insists that it be gradual and unplanned.
It opposes radical change imposed on a society by utopian visionaries on the basis of a sweeping
theory of “social justice.” The radical’s confidence that certain long established social practices
are irrational or unjust and that the practices with which he would replace them would be better is
supposed to make him both arrogant and irresponsible. After examining BC’s presumption more
closely, this paper identifies three possible ways to defend it—the entrenchment thesis; a
historical survey that supports the backlash principle; and the optimality thesis—and argues that
all of them fail.
Burke; What the Conservative Presumption Entails
A plea for deference to tradition is one of the outstanding themes of Edmund Burke’s
Reflections on the Revolution in France. France’s philosophes propounded many theories that
contributed to the French Revolution (e.g. Abbé Sieyès is supposed to have instructed the French
Assembly to “act like men just emerging from the state of nature and coming together for the
purpose of signing a social contract”1), and Burke objected that their theories were both false and
dangerous. One of the most famous passages in his Reflections is where he contrasts the
intellectual hubris of France’s revolutionaries to the humility of the English:
We are not the converts of Rousseau; we are not the disciples of Voltaire; Helvetius has
made no progress amongst us. Atheists are not our preachers; mad men are not our
lawgivers. We know that we have made no discoveries ; and we think that no discoveries
are to be made, in morality; nor many in the great principles of government …. [W]e are
generally men of untaught feelings; … instead of casting away all our old prejudices, we
cherish them to a very considerable degree…. [W]e cherish them b ecause they are
prejudices; and the longer they have lasted, and the more generally they have prevailed,
pf3
pf4
pf5
pf8
pf9
pfa
pfd
pfe
pff

Partial preview of the text

Download Edmund Burke's Conservative Presumption: Tradition, Deference, and the Harm Principle and more Lecture notes Law in PDF only on Docsity!

Burkean Conservatism and the Presumption in Favor of Tradition At the heart of conservative political thought lies its plea for deference to the political structure, particular laws, and moral norms of a society that are old and established. Burkean conservatism (BC) does not oppose all social change, but insists that it be gradual and unplanned. It opposes radical change imposed on a society by utopian visionaries on the basis of a sweeping theory of “social justice.” The radical’s confidence that certain long established social practices are irrational or unjust and that the practices with which he would replace them would be better is supposed to make him both arrogant and irresponsible. After examining BC’s presumption more closely, this paper identifies three possible ways to defend it—the entrenchment thesis; a historical survey that supports the backlash principle; and the optimality thesis—and argues that all of them fail. Burke; What the Conservative Presumption Entails A plea for deference to tradition is one of the outstanding themes of Edmund Burke’s Reflections on the Revolution in France. France’s philosophes propounded many theories that contributed to the French Revolution (e.g. Abbé Sieyès is supposed to have instructed the French Assembly to “act like men just emerging from the state of nature and coming together for the purpose of signing a social contract”^1 ), and Burke objected that their theories were both false and dangerous. One of the most famous passages in his Reflections is where he contrasts the intellectual hubris of France’s revolutionaries to the humility of the English: We are not the converts of Rousseau; we are not the disciples of Voltaire; Helvetius has made no progress amongst us. Atheists are not our preachers; madmen are not our lawgivers. We know that we have made no discoveries; and we think that no discoveries are to be made, in morality; nor many in the great principles of government …. [W]e are generally men of untaught feelings; … instead of casting away all our old prejudices, we cherish them to a very considerable degree…. [W]e cherish them because they are prejudices; and the longer they have lasted, and the more generally they have prevailed,

the more we cherish them. We are afraid to put men to live and trade each on his own private stock of reason; because we suspect that this stock in each man is small, and that the individuals would be better to avail themselves of the general bank and capital of nations, and of ages…. Your literary men, and your politicians, and so do the whole clan of the enlightened among us, essentially differ in these points. They have no respect for the wisdom of others; but they pay it off by a very full measure of confidence in their own. With them it is sufficient motive to destroy an old scheme of things, because it is an old one. As to the new, they are in no sort of fear with regard to the duration of a building run up in haste…. 2 BC’s presumption in favor of tradition obviously implies that violent revolution should be avoided. A rebellion against a tyrant who usurps power in some unconstitutional way and then trammels on people’s long recognized rights is okay. But a revolution isn’t simply armed rebellion; it is (as in the French and Russian cases) a radical transformation of a society’s political structure. Revolutions unleash forces that can easily spin out of control and lead to anarchy, or even worse, an organized reign of terror. The presumption in favor of political and legal tradition applies not just to society’s political structure, but its particular laws too. Recently the Florida legislature enacted a statute that amends the common law requirements for self-defense. “Necessity” has always been a requirement for the justified use of lethal force; where flight is possible, this requirement for self- defense is not met. (An exception is if one is attacked in one’s home). The Florida law (dubbed by its supporters the “Stand Your Ground” law) essentially does away with the “flee if you can” requirement altogether, eliminating the duty to prefer escape to a lethal response if one is attacked in a public place. Florida’s action surely violates BC’s presumption of deference to long standing legal traditions. Its legislature overrode an old, evolved, common law principle of justified homicide not in response to any urgent need, but because Second Amendment, gun rights ideologues felt that the “flee if you safely can” principle imposed an undue burden on law- abiding citizens. BC condemns Florida’s action on the grounds that it is likely to have many bad consequences, some unforeseeable and some (e.g. an increase in the deaths of innocent bystanders caught in the crossfire) not.

prostitution for the libertarian) should be amended not because they are old, but because they restrict liberty.^4 Two ways of defending the presumption are by inferring it from either the “optimality thesis” (OT) or the “entrenchment thesis” (ET). According to OT, long standing social practices got to be long standing because they served the needs of society and its members better than any other practices could. They were and continue to be optimal. ET, in contrast, admits that many social practices became established due to historical contingencies and are unlikely to be optimific in the promotion of welfare. Still, long standing social practices have become integral parts of the social order, part of its foundations, and any attempt to modify them is likely to damage the social edifice which rests on them. A common way of developing ET is in conjunction with a communitarian sociology. It alleges that while the radical’s intent may be to replace one set of norms with a different set, the more likely effect of his actions is to destroy the existing ones without replacing them with anything viable. That produces anomic, rudderless individuals who act in anti-social ways. A society with too many such persons is likely to experience increased divorce, drug and alcohol abuse, and teenage pregnancy; higher dropout rates; less saving (due to an unwillingness to delay gratification); more violent crime; and other social pathologies. BC sees traditional morality buttressed by traditional theistic religious belief as society’s most effective way of staving off these maladies. Not only does fear of punishment in the afterlife deter socially destructive acts in the here and now, but the communal aspect of organized religious worship encourages a sense of responsibility to a larger social group. Given the desirability of preventing the harm caused by more divorce, higher crime, and the rest, ET (if true) justifies criminalizing acts that threaten to weaken or destroy any of society’s long standing moral or religious traditions. Patrick Devlin accepted this implication of ET with his defense of traditional morals legislation (e.g. anti-sodomy laws). Devlin held that “society may use the law to preserve morality in the same way as it uses it to safeguard anything else that is essential to its existence.”^5 Criminalizing acts that are repugnant to the moral sensibilities of

the average person (“the man in the Clapham omnibus") is permissible, Devlin held, for the same reason that criminalizing attempts at political subversion is. ET has anti-liberal implications more extreme than either Devlin or the defender of BC intends. Traditional Judeo-Christian views about “unnatural sex” are surely in greater danger of being undermined by public criticism that they reflect mere homophobia than by clandestine homosexual couplings. Hence, his argument should lead him to support a ban on any public criticism of established moral norms. But Devlin only wanted to defend anti-sodomy laws, not the censorship of moral debate too. This implication of ET prevents BC from appealing to it to justify its presumption. BC might support some traditional morals laws, but it certainly opposes any use of the criminal law to punish criticism of traditional morals or the advocacy of nontraditional moral views. Indeed, it has to oppose it, since a rejection of viewpoint-based censorship is a long standing legal tradition in countries like the U.S. and Great Britain. Inferring the Presumption from a Historical Survey We’ll consider OT shortly. Another possible way to defend the causal claims [i) and ii) above] that underlie BC’s presumption is to argue that a historical survey of radical political reforms and of individuals’ moral nonconformism reveals that they are almost always followed by bad consequences, and these correlations are strong evidence for the corresponding causal claims. But this strategy encounters a problem: how do we know whether the long term effects of any example of a radical political action were on balance good or bad for society? The French Revolution, for example, did unleash a Reign of Terror, one of its bad consequences, but it also eliminated many feudal obstacles to capitalist economic development and spread a Napoleonic legal code throughout much of Europe—two of its good ones. Did those good consequences outweigh the bad ones? The difficulty presented by this example is that not only are we unsure which of the events following the French Revolution were caused by it rather than other,

a historical survey of past radical actions supports the backlash principle, and the desirability of avoiding sometimes violent backlashes supports the presumption in favor of tradition. There are two problems with such an argument. First, any critique of radical politics that’s based on the backlash principle is too limited for BC. For example, it will be unable to explain what’s wrong with Florida’s “Stand Your Ground” law. What makes that law radical is its willingness to disregard common law principles that have evolved over hundreds of years, not its attempt to ram any moral ideals currently rejected by Floridians down their throats. BC implies that this law is likely to have bad consequences even if it does not provoke a strong backlash (which seems unlikely in any case). A critique of radical politics based solely on the backlash principle cannot account for BC’s disapproval of laws like it. Second, there is no reason why the radical has to be blind to the potential that his reforms, if wrongly implemented, will provoke a backlash. And even if a backlash is unavoidable, it is only one cost that the prudent radical will be sure to include in his cost-benefit calculations. The radical can say that some radical reforms are likely to elicit strong backlashes, others weak ones, and we should decide on a case-by-case basis whether the negative effects of the backlash are likely to outweigh the positive effects of the radical reform. Compare Brown v. Board of Education and a possible ruling by the U.S. Supreme Court that state bans on gay marriage violate Equal Protection. Both are examples of “radical” politics. The first did produce a strong backlash, and the second probably would too were the Court ever to deliver it. With the first we have the benefit of historical hindsight, and in hindsight we can say that even though Brown provoked an often violent backlash from racist whites determined to hold on to their traditions of de jure racial segregation, it played an important role in weakening the racial caste system. My sense is that even before the Brown ruling was handed down, opponents of segregation were justified in believing that Supreme Court invalidation of Jim Crow laws would be best for the country in the long run, despite the violent backlash that such a ruling was certain to cause. Is the same true of a Supreme Court ruling requiring all states to recognize

gay marriage? Cass Sunstein, a strong advocate of gay rights and no champion of “judicial conservatism,” thinks not. He writes “under contemporary conditions, a judicial holding of this sort would probably be a large mistake, even though the basic principle is sound…. [In] producing social reform in this area, public officials should be selective, strategic, and occasionally cautious.” 7 I agree with Sunstein: the likelihood of an extreme backlash against gay rights is too great to risk such a ruling at this time. The cause of gay rights is better served by a more gradualist approach. These judgments about Brown and a gay marriage ruling are based on a cautious, strategic radicalism that acknowledges the political reality of backlashes. Again, BC will object that it is intellectual hubris to think that one can reliably gauge the strength of a potential backlash and accurately weigh a radical action’s long term costs and benefits. But again, that charge is based on the conservative’s judgment that the dangers of making such judgments outweigh the potential benefits, and that judgment will be no easier to defend that ones that the radical makes. It won’t do for the conservative to respond that when he performs the historical survey of past radical actions and their consequences, he relies only on hindsight, while the radical has to rely on foresight, and hindsight is inherently more reliable than foresight. With hindsight we can know what happened, but that alone will not tell us why it happened. To be justified in believing that a historical survey supports the presumption, the conservative needs to make judgments about cause and effect and about the relative weight of costs vs. benefits that are no different in kind from the ones that the radical makes. The fact that those judgments are about events in the past does not make them any easier to defend. The Optimality Thesis and the Invisible Hand A third possible way to defend the presumption is by inferring it from the optimality thesis. OT proposes a functional explanation of a society’s moral and legal traditions: they exist because they are good for society as a whole. It implies that the radical who wants to tinker with

supplying society’s myriad economic needs, with fewer shortages or surpluses, than private property and free exchange in competitive markets would. While there’s no doubt about the reality of the economist’s invisible hand, it cannot provide what OT needs. The economist’s invisible hand operates only within the legal and moral rules that create a capitalist economic system. What OT needs is an invisible hand that explains the social utility of old and established social/legal rules in all societies. Clearly the economist’s invisible hand, which presupposes the existence and enforcement of one particular set of social/legal rules, cannot even explain how those very rules came about, much less the social/legal rules of noncapitalist societies. Another possible candidate for the invisible hand mechanism needed by OT is one that is the social analogue of Darwinian natural selection in biology. The social analogue of natural selection wouldn’t require that societies have “offspring” that inherit some of their traits. It only implies that they are in competition with one another and that the ones with rules that promote solidarity, technological progress, military prowess, and so forth are more likely to prevail in that competition. The fact that a society has survived for centuries is evidence that its rules are adaptive to its survival. F.A. Hayek has defended an invisible hand mechanism of this sort, though the one he defends is supposed to operate only on voluntary moral norms, not coercive laws.^9 Perhaps the main problem with trying to defend BC’s presumption by appealing to a sociological analogue to Darwinian natural selection is that it requires an inference from “group A with its norm forbidding X has over time grown more numerous/stronger, while group B with no proscription on X has over time fared less well” to “group A has grown bigger and stronger because of its proscription on X.” That inference either commits the post hoc, ergo proctor hoc fallacy, or it makes the same mistake that “Panglossian adaptationism” makes in biology.^10 The latter is the mistake of supposing that every trait of an organism has been selected because it somehow enhances its fitness. The fact is that some of our traits (e.g. the birth canal) are

imperfectly adaptive and others (e.g. the appendix) are maladaptive. If social evolution is similar to natural selection, then traditional morality’s proscription on homosexuality, for example, could be more like the human birth canal or the panda’s thumb (a bone spur rather than an opposable digit, which just barely serves the panda’s needs) or even our appendix than a highly adaptive trait like the echolocation of bats. The invisible hand of social evolution no more guarantees that all gradually evolved practices are beneficial to society than Darwinian natural selection guarantees that every single one of our inherited traits enhances our biological fitness. Recall that OT, if true, supports an analogy between the radical social reformer eager to abolish some long standing practice, on the one hand, and the doctor who wants to remove my spleen because he can’t see what good it does me. That analogy is flawed, however, because we know that the spleen plays a role in the immune system, making possession of it adaptive. Why not think that the radical social reformer is at least sometimes is more like the surgeon who wants to perform an appendectomy before the patient’s appendix ruptures? To push the analogy a bit further, opposition to all radical politics, based on the conviction that all old and established laws benefit society in ways that we can’t fully understand, looks like the dogmatic insistence that “natural” therapies are always better for the patient than surgery and drugs. A third candidate for the mechanism by which OT’s invisible hand operates is divine providence. If an omniscient and benevolent God guides the selection of norms and laws in any society, then OT is true and BC’s presumption is warranted. In that case the radical reformer is analogous not so much to the economic planner in a command economy or the doctor who wants to remove my spleen, but the impious and arrogant fool who doubts that God exists and knows what He is doing.^11 The objection to this view is obvious. Many tradition bound societies seem to have honor codes that hinder their ability to modernize. In some very patriarchal societies (e.g. rural Afghanistan) fathers and brothers have the duty to kill a daughter or sister who has brought dishonor to the family by carrying on an illicit romance. In other societies young women must

optimality thesis that posits an invisible hand. The failure of all three defenses suggests that BC cannot sustain its charge of arrogance and irresponsibility against the radical. (^1) Quoted by F.A. Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (University of Chicago Press, 1960), p. 57. Hayek cites J.L. Talmon, The Origins of Totalitarian Democracy (London, 1952), p. 73. (^2) Edmund Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France (Penguin Books, 1982), pp. 114 - 15. (^3) Burke in particular has been described as an “indirect utilitarian” by Jeremy Waldron and a “historical utilitarian” by Jerry Muller. See Jeremy Waldron, Nonsense on Stilts (London: Methuen, 1987), pp. 87-89 and Muller’s essay “What is Conservative Social and Political Thought?” in Jerry Z. Muller (ed.) Conservatism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997), p. 7. (^4) Michael Oakeshott makes the same mistake as Burke. He describes the “Rationalist” as someone who “believes that to form a habit is to fail” (p. 7) and regards “the consciously planned and deliberately executed [to be] for that reason better than what has grown up and established itself unconsciously over a period of time” (p. 26). Michael Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays (Indianapolis, Liberty Press: 1991). It should be noted that the fact of human fallibility and limited knowledge by itself provides no argument for BC’s presumption. All that follows from it is that human actions have many unintended and unforeseen consequences. It does not follow, even if we are referring to actions that violate well-entrenched moral and legal traditions, that those consequences are more likely to be negative than positive. It’s that claim about the effects of ignoring tradition that the conservative needs to defend. Knowing that one’s judgment is fallible and one’s experience limited by itself provides no reason to believe it.

(^5) Patrick Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals (London: Oxford University Press, 1965), p.

(^6) The “backlash principle” is related to what Albert O. Hirshman has called the “thesis of the perverse effect,” which he has argued is a recurrent theme of reactionary politics over several centuries. (^7) Cass Sunstein, “Homosexuality and the Constitution,” in David M. Estlund and Martha Nussbaum (eds.), Sex, Preference, and Family (Oxford Univ. Press, 1997); anthologized in David M. Adams, Philosophical Problems in the Law 4 th^ ed (Wadsworth Press, 2005), p. 326. (^8) Conservatism, according to Irving Kristol, assumes that “institutions which have existed over a long period of time have a reason and a purpose inherent in them, a collective wisdom incarnate in them, and the fact that we don’t perfectly understand or cannot perfectly explain why they ‘work’ is no defect in them but merely a limitation in us.” Irving Kristol, “Utopianism, Ancient and Modern,” in Two Cheers for Capitalism (New York, 1978), p. 161. Kristol’s conservatism, I claim, requires a commitment to OT and belief in an invisible hand. (^9) Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty , Chapters Four and Five. (^10) See Stephen J. Gould and Richard Lewontin, “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme,” Proceedings of the Royal Society v. B205 (1979), pp. 581-598. (^11) This view should not be confused with the patriotic myth that America has been the object of divine favor since its Founding and been given the responsibility to spread democracy and capitalism throughout the world (its “Manifest Destiny”). America’s Founding myth implies that God shows favor only to some societies. OT based on a divine providence invisible hand mechanism implies that God is at work in all societies to ensure that only socially beneficial moral and legal traditions get to be old and established.